Kyle Johnson

Case # 46
Gapping

Gapping is an ellipsis in which a verb is removed in one, or more, of a series of coördinations. (1) is emblematic.

(1) Some ate beans and others, rice.

The name comes from Ross 1970, who appears to be the first to have systematically studied the process. The set of cases for which Gapping is responsible remains controversial, though there is consensus on a certain range of them. A more or less standard criterion is that Gapping occurs only in coördinate structures. The two main candidates that don't meet this requirement, but which nonetheless superficially appear to be instances of Gapping, are list-like answers to questions, like those in (2), and comparative constructions, like those in (3).1

(2) Q: Who met who?
  A: Jerry, Sarah; Sally, Mark; Trish, Betsy
(3) Sally met more parents than kids.

Many treatments of Gapping - most modern ones - leave these cases out, and so shall I in what follows.

If Gapping is restricted to coördinations, then one task is to determine whether Gapping is a special instance of one of the many forms of ellipsis found in coördinations, or, if it isn't, how to distinguish it from the others. This problem looms large because Gapping is commonly credited with being able to elide more than just the finite verb. Ross, for example, gave it the ability to elide the quite remarkable set of strings in (4).

(4) a. I want to try to begin to write a novel and Mary wants to try to begin to write a play.
  b. ?I want to try to begin to write a novel, and Mary wants to try to begin to write a play.
c. ?I want to try to begin to write a novel, and Mary wants to try to begin to write a play.
d. ?I want to try to begin to write a novel, and Mary wants to try to begin to write a play.
  (Ross 1970 (2c): 250)

(Strike-outs will indicate elided material, from here out.) In fact, however, there is a sharp degradation in these particular examples that favors (4a) over the others. I suspect this is because in (4b)-(4c) material left behind by Gapping matches that in the antecedent clause; in general, these "remnants," must contrast with parallel terms in the antecedent clause, as we shall see below. If this property of (4b)-(4c) is remedied, the result is improved.

(5) a. I want to try to begin to write a novel, and Mary wants to try to begin to review a play.
  b. I want to try to begin to write a novel, and Mary wants to try to set-out to review a play.
  c. I want to try to begin to write a novel, and Mary wants to get ready to set-out to review a play.

There remains some awkwardness, especially in (5b) and (5c), perhaps because of the strain involved in contrasting so many terms.

Nonetheless, in principle these strings are Gappable, and this raises the possibility that Gapping could figure in a wide range of coördinations. It might be responsible for creating (6a) or (6b).

(6) a. Jerry met the kids from OshKosh and Sally scrutinized the kids from OshKosh.
  b. Sam ate and Sam was put to bed.

(6a) is an example of what Postal 1974 called "Right Node Raising," which here removes the object of the first conjunct. There are two potential, non-gapping, sources for (6b). It could be that there is an elision process, as indicated, distinct from Gapping which removes material at the edges of a coördinate. That such a process, what Ross 1967 calls "Forward Conjunction Reduction," exists has been widely speculated. The other potential source would deny that there is any ellipsis at all, and instead let the VPs ate and was put to bed conjoin to jointly take Sam as subject. Both treatments have their problems, and evidence distinguishing them is difficult to find.2

One feature that distinguishes (1), (4) and (5) from (6) is that the clause holding the Gap in (1), (4) and (5) contains remnant material at the left and right edges, but this isn't so in (6). Jackendoff 1971 suggests that this should be taken as a defining trait of Gapping.

Restricting Gapping in this way, however, is not how Ross would have done it. The goal of his paper, in fact, is to defend the thesis that the conjunct in which a verb is Gapped is determined by the linear position that that verb would have to other terms in its sentence if it hadn't elided. Ross suggests that if the verb would precede its complements, then it will Gap from the second, or subsequent, conjuncts, and the first conjunct will hold the antecedent. If the verb follows its complements, on the other hand, then it will Gap from the initial conjuncts, and the antecedent will be found in the final one. So, for instance, he suggests that in languages, like Japanese and Russian, where a complement may precede its verb, Gapping is responsible for producing sentences such as (7).

(7) a. Watakusi-wa. sakana-o tabe Biru-wa gohan-o tabeta (Japanese)
  I-Top fish-ACC eat beer-TOP rice-ACC ate  
'I ate fish and Bill, rice.'
  b. Ja vodu pila i Anna vodku pila (Russian)
  I water drank and Anna vodka drank  
'I drank wanter and Anna, vodka.'
  (Ross 1970 (5b), (10b): 251)

In such cases, of course, the Gapped verb makes up the right edge of the clause it has been elided from, and this violates Jackendoff's criterion.

Further, if Jackendoff's criterion is relaxed, then examples like (8) could also be seen as instances of Gapping.

(8) Mary left early, and Sally left early too.

In this case, the finite verb of the second conjunct would have Gapped along with the adverb early, and removed all of the second conjunct except its subject. Gapping might also be credited with (9), which could be seen as a special instance of the forward conjunct reduction case in (6b).

(9) Jill ate rice yesterday and Jill ate porridge today.

Note that unlike (6b), however, the analysis which denies any ellipsis in (9) is less plausible. Such an account would have to treat rice yesterday and porridge today as constituents.

In fact, Jackendoff's criterion is not generally adopted, and some of these cases are reasonably classed as Gapping. But for examples like (6a), the consensus appears to be that they are not, in fact, Gapping. Some superficial differences between cases of Right Node Raising, and canonical instances of Gapping, like those in (1), are the following.

Gapping allows a mismatch in inflectional class between the Gapped verb and its antecedent; but Right Node Raising resists this.

(10) a. He likes beans and you like rice.
  b. *He always complains and you sometimes complain.

Right Node Raising is able to remove part of a word, as in (11b), but Gapping isn't.

(11) a. *Carly is overpaid and Will underpaid.
  b. Carly is overpaid, and Will underpaid

Right Node Raising needs the material it elides to make up a contiguous string, but Gapping can (apparently) elide discontinuous strings, as the contrast in (12) illustrates.

(12) a. Carrie gave a set of directions to me, and Will gave a map to me.
  b. *Carrie gave a set of directions to me, and Will gave a map to me.

And Right Node Raising can strand prepositions, but Gapping can't (a point made in Neijt 1979):

(13) a. *John is confident of a successful outing and Peter is dependent on a successful outing.
  b. John is confident of a successful outing and Peter is dependent on a successful outing.
  (Neijt 1979 (85a), (86a): 40)

Hankamer 1979 Chapter 1 and Maling 1972 argue that finite verb ellipsis in verb final languages, like Turkish, is actually Right Node Raising. The jury is still out on languages like Japanese; but in general, there appears to be no uniformly agreed upon instance of Gapping applying to delete material in the first conjunct, in the way that Ross suggested.

The cases in (8) and (9), on the other hand, are better candidates for Gapping. The case in (9) can be put together with examples like (14), in which various kinds of phrases follow the left conjunct.3

(14) a. Did you tell John about our plans or Peter?
  (Ross 1967, p. 244)
  b. Sally talked about the meeting passionately and about its consequences too.
  c. James left unhappy today and unappreciated too.

Ross 1967 analyzed these as involving extraposition of a phrase consisting of and or or and the string that follows it. (14b), for instance, would have a source like Sally talked about the meeting and about its consequences too passionately, and would be formed by moving the underlined phrase to the end of the sentence.4 But Neijt 1979 argues that they derive instead from Gapping; so (14b) would come from something like (15).

(15) Sally talked about the meeting passionately, and Sally talked about its consequences too.

One of her arguments on behalf of the Gapping interpretation is that it could make sense of the fact that examples like (16) are blocked.

(16) *That dress has been designed by my grandma and made.
    (Neijt 1979 (141a):64)

There is no obvious reason why this shouldn't be derived from That dress has been designed and made by my grandma, under Ross's analysis. But if Gapping must always include the verb, and we shall see evidence for this shortly, then the ungrammaticality of (16) would be explained if its source is Gapping.

Another reason for believing that some form of ellipsis produces examples such as (9) and (14) is that it could also create examples such as (17).

(17) Betsy wanted to read a book or a magazine.

In fact, (17) has a meaning which is suggestive of such a source. On one reading, (17) describes a particular desire that Betsy has: she desires to read something that is either a book or a magazine. But on another of its readings, (17) is synonymous with (18), which claims that Betsy has one or the other of two desires.

(18) Betsy wanted to read a book or Betsy wanted to read a magazine.

This second reading for (17) would be a straightforward consequence of deleting from the second disjunct of (18) Betsy wanted to read. Schwarz 1999 argues for this conclusion, and notes that it makes sense of the fact that (19) gets only this latter reading.

(19) Either Betsy wanted to read a book or a magazine.

This follows from the plausible thesis that either marks the left edge of a disjunction, which would force (19) to be a disjunction of clauses from which all but the object has Gapped in the second clause.

These are reasons, then, for believing that ellipsis can produce examples like (9), (14) and (17); and given Neijt's argument from (16), Gapping is probably the form of ellipsis responsible.5 But note that for cases like (17), it is not necessary that Gapping be the only source. It is consistent with standard views of coördination that (17) could arise by disjoining a book and a magazine in the embedded clause. And this, or something like it, could be the appropriate representation for this sentence when it gets the first of the interpretations described (i.e., Betsy has a desire to read a book or a magazine).

To see the reason for classifying (8) as a Gapping construction, it is necessary first to appreciate one of the constraints that controls which strings can Gap. Hankamer 1979 discovered that Gapping cannot affect a verb that is in an embedded clause, as in (20).6

(20) *Alfonse stole the emeralds, and I think that Mugsy stole the pearls.
  (Hankamer 1979 (23): 19)

He noted also that the antecedent to a Gap cannot be in an embedded clause. (21) illustrates.

(21) *I think that Alfonse stole the emeralds, and Mugsy stole the pearls.

If (21) is understood as a (somewhat awkward) conjunction of two clauses, rather than as a single clause with an embedded coördination, it is ungrammatical. Now, when Ross's examples in (4) are considered, we can see that there is nothing wrong with a verb in an embedded clause being part of the Gapped material or its antecedent. Rather, what the contrast between (20) and (21) shows is that the Gapped material, and its antecedent, must include the verb of the conjoined clauses. In fact, it is likely that this constraint is even stronger, preventing a Gap or its antecedent from excluding the highest verb of the conjuncts, so I will formulate it as in (22).

(22) The No Embedding Constraint
  Let A and B be conjoined or disjoined phrases, and β be the string elided in B whose antecedent is α in A. Then α and β must contain the highest verb in A and B.

It's this constraint that forms the foundation for Neijt's argument from the ungrammaticality of (16) that (9) and (14) are created by Gapping. Because the No Embedding Constraint requires Gapping to elide at least the verb, it'll block (16). And, note too, that the No Embedding Constraint would also prevent Gapping from being able to create (6b), since the verbs of the second conjunct remain in this example.

The validity of the No Embedding Constraint turns then on whether (6b) should be classed as a Gapping construction, and also on whether examples such as (23) are instances of Gapping.

(23) Some have eaten chocolate, and others might eat fruit.

Levin 1986 argued that cases like (23) are produced by an ellipsis process distinct from Gapping, dubbing it "Pseudogapping," to enforce her conclusion. Pseudogapping differs from Gapping in being able to apply in contexts other than coördinations, as in (24).

(24) Sally should eat legumes because she won't eat broccoli.

Furthermore, there are languages which have Gapping, but which don't allow Pseudogapping. German is such a language, as the contrast between (25a) and (25b) indicates.

(25) a. Sally hat Kumquats gegessen und Dieter Bier getrunken
    Sally has kumquats eaten and Dieter beer drank
'Sally ate kumquats and Dieter drank beer.'
 
b. *Sally hat Kumquats gegessen weil Dieter Natto hat
  Sally has kumquats eaten since Dieter natto has
  'Sally ate kumquats because Dieter natto.'

And German examples parallel to (23) are ungrammatical, again suggesting that these cases cannot be produced by Gapping.

(26) *Sally. hat Kumquats gegessen und Dieter hat Natto
  Sally. has kumquats eaten and Dieter has natto
  'Sally ate kumquats and Dieter natto.'

For this reason, then, I'll adopt a formulation of Hankamer's constraint like that in (22), and assume that neither (6b) nor (23) arise through Gapping.

So far as is known, Gapping is the only ellipsis process constrained by the No Embedding Constraint. To the extent that the No Embedding Constraint is unique to Gapping, then, it can be used as a diagnostic for it. And, according to this diagnostic, examples such as (8) are produced from Gapping. When the second conjunct in (8) is embedded under a verb, as in (27), the result is ungrammatical.

(27) *Mary left early, and I think Sally too.

Putting together these various observations, we can formulate a preliminary definition of Gapping as follows.

(28) Gapping
  In a structure A cB, where c is and or or, Gapping deletes a string in B that is identical to a string in A and satisfies the No Embedding Constraint (i.e., (22)).

This captures the fact that Gapping is restricted to coördinations (with the caveat about (2) and (3)), removes material from the second of two conjuncts, and is subject to Hankamer's No Embedding Constraint. It also entails, because of the requirements in the No Embedding Constraint, that Gapping can only elide verbs. Neijt 1979 argues that this outcome is correct as well, citing examples such as those in (29) to illustrate that Gapping is prevented from applying to Prepositions, Adjectives and Quantifiers.

(29) a. *Several inches above the ground and several feet above sea level.
  b. *A five year younger or 10 year younger sister.
c. *He ran a few seconds faster or a few minutes faster to his house.
d. *Bill drank much too much or a little bit too much wine.
e. *John bought a little bit more or a lot more.
  (Neijt 1979 (54c,e-h), p. 27)

And though there are cases, like (30), which look as though they could be achieved if Gapping applies to Nouns, she suggests that these are the products of another ellipsis process, " Deletion," exemplified by examples such as (31).7

(30) One dog with five legs, another dog with a cow's liver, and a third dog with no head.
  (Neijt 1979 (54a), p. 27)
 
(31) One dog with five legs walked in after another dog with no head left.

Setting aside the issue of Nouns, it should be noted, however, that there are contexts in which Adjectives would appear to be able to Gap:

(32) a. Malfoy made Snape happy about his potions and Hagrid happy about his Griffons.
  b. Hermoine considered Voldemort frightened of Dumbledore and Malfoy frightened of Harry.

So far as I have been able to determine, other categories are not susceptible to Gapping in these contexts, however:

(33) a. *Ron let Harry in the dungeon and Filtch in the common room.
  b. *Dudley considers some witches friends of mine and others friends of yours.

Let us continue to restrict Gapping to strings with verbs in them, then, pending an explanation for the exceptional cases in (32).8

There is another, somewhat subtler, consequence of defining Gapping as (28) does. Because (28) requires that the antecedent to a Gapped string be found in the conjunct or disjunct immediately preceding, it will prevent a Gap from finding a more distant antecedent in situations in which there are more than two coördinates. It will correctly prevent examples such as (34), for instance.

(34) *John invited Sue, Peter kissed Mary, and Max invited Betsy.
    (Neijt 1979 note 7 (iv), p. 71)

Because the antecedent to invited is not found in the immediately preceding conjunct, it cannot Gap in the final conjunct. On the other hand, an example such as (35) is permitted, as Gapping can apply from right to left, taking the conjuncts pairwise.

(35) John invited Sue, Peter invited Mary, and Max invited Betsy.

So, the Gapped invited in the final conjunct finds its antecedent in the immediately preceding conjunct, and this middle invited in turn Gaps under identity with the antecedent in the first conjunct.

Let's turn next to the question of how to characterize the set of strings that Gapping can elide. As we have seen in (5) and (12) - repeated below - Gapping can delete strings of terms that are not typically thought to make up constituents in English.

(36) a. I want to try to begin to write a novel and Mary wants to try to begin to review a play.
  b. Carrie gave a set of directions to me, and Will gave a map to me.

Standard parses of English sentences do not form a constituent of want to try to begin that excludes to review a play; nor do they allow discontinuous strings, like the gave to me sequence in (36b), to form a constituent that excludes intervening material. Because syntactic processes are very typically restricted to affecting just constituents, these cases are surprising. If we think of Gapping as a rule that targets strings in a clause and deletes them, then this would be a counterexample to this otherwise valid generalization about such rules.

But it's not that Gapping can delete just any string. Hankamer 1979, for example, observes that there are contrasts like (37).

(37) a. Charley writes with a pencil and John writes with a pen.
  b. *Charley writes with a pencil and John writes with a pen.
  *Charley writes with a pencil and John writes with a pen.
  (Hankamer 1979, p. 18)

It appears that Gapping is prevented from taking part of a preposition phrase and leaving the rest. And, similarly, Gapping cannot elide a portion of an object noun phrase either, as in (38).

(38) a. Charley wrote several books on syntax and Jill wrote several books on semantics.
  b. *Charley wrote several books on syntax and Jill wrote several books on semantics.
  c. *Charley wrote several books on syntax and Jill wrote several books on semantics.

There have been two broad approaches to capturing constraints such as these. In one, generalizations about the shape that the remnants may have are sought; and in the other, generalizations about the elided strings themselves are formulated.

Hankamer's own approach was of the first kind. He described the constraint responsible for (37) and (38) in terms of a restriction that requires the remnants of Gapping to be "Major Constituents," which he defined as phrases which are immediate daughters of S (or IP, in modern parlance). Because he held a skeptical view about the existence of VP, this meant that subjects, adverbs, PPs and objects qualified as Major Constituents, but nothing else. If we admit the existence of VP, we might formulate this along the lines he resorts to in Hankamer 1973 page 18: "A 'major constituent' of a given sentence S0 is a constituent either immediately dominated by S0, or immediately dominated by VP which is immediately dominated by S0." That we should allow Gapping to see VPs, and therefore adopt this formulation, is indicated by cases such as (39), in which an auxiliary verb has elided.

(39) Some have prepared kumquats and others have baked pies.

While the status of examples such as (39) is somewhat controversial - Ross 1970 classed them as ungrammatical, and Siegel 1987, where they are marked grammatical, assumes that they are not produced by Gapping - the present consensus appears to be that they are both grammatical and Gapping. That they are Gapping is suggested by the fact that they appear to meet the criteria (28) uses to define Gapping. For example, auxiliary verbs may delete like this only in coördinations (compare (40a)), the antecedent must be in the first coördinate (witness (40b)), and it is subject to the No Embedding Constraint (as (40c) suggests).

(40) a. *Some have prepared kumquats while others have baked pies.
  b. *Some have prepared kumquats and others have baked pies.
c. *Some wanted to have prepared kumquats, and others wanted to have baked pies.

To the extent that (39) is grammatical, then, it shows that Gapping can leave the verb+NP string as a remnant. We have already seen, however, that the auxiliary verb+NP string in (41) does not constitute a legitimate Gapping remnant (this sentence, to the extent that it is grammatical, comes about by way of pseudogapping.)

(41) Some have prepared kumquats and others have prepared pies.

Thus, we seek a way of distinguishing these two cases. That is, in a string have+participle+NP, we want to allow participle+NP to be able to survive as a remnant from Gapping, but prevent have+NP from being a remnant. While it may not be utterly necessary, it seems reasonable to adopt the commonplace view that the participle+NP string is embedded within the have+participle+NP string, and distinguish them that way. (This is just what the No Embedding Constraint, in fact, does.) But this will require the existence of VPs. Thus we should adopt the definition of major constituent that recognizes the existence of VPs.

Hankamer's constraint hasn't been widely adopted. One straightforward difficulty is that the notion "major constituent" has not been grounded in anything more general. That is, so far as other syntactic processes are concerned, major constituents don't appear to behave as a class, making their use in constraining Gapping somewhat dubious. Moreover, there seem to be counterexamples to Hankamer's constraint. Sag points out,9 for instance, that it would not permit instances of Gapping like those in (36a), repeated in (42a), and it's hard to see how to modify the constraint so that it could distinguish (42a) from (42b).

(42) a. I want to try to begin to write a novel and Mary wants to try to begin to review a play.
  b. *I want to try to begin to write a novel and Mary wants to try to begin to review a play.

There is, however, evidence that the remnants to Gapping must be able to be factored into constituents. And, indeed, it is likely that they must be partitionable into maximal projections. This would explain the contrast between (38a) and (38b), as well as that between (37b) and (37c). And it would extend to account for the badness of examples such as (43).

(43) a. *Some read angry letters and others read angry reports.
  b. *Some bought books about themselves and others bought reports about themselves.
c. *Some remember your mother and others remember your father.
d. *Some brought every package and others brought every wrapper.
e. *Some appeared almost happy and others appear almost rich.
f. *Some talked only to Smith and others talked only to Jones.

In each of the examples in (43), a subconstituent of the noun phrase, adjective phrase or prepositional phrase has survived Gapping. If the material that would make these subconstituents full NPs, APs or PPs is restored, the examples become grammatical. Let's adopt, then, this rather watered down version of Hankamer's condition on remnants:

(44) The Constituency Condition of Remnants
  Let P(x) be a parse for a string x. If A is a string of words in a coördinate, from which the substring B has Gapped leaving the string C, then there must be a way of factoring C into a series of maximal projections found in P(A).

This leaves the ungrammaticality of (37b) and (38c,d) to be explained; and also fails to shed light on the contrast between (42a) and (42b). We will review below a way of deriving the Constituency Condition that extends to these cases.

Another proposed constraint on remnants is that there may be no more than two of them.10 Jackendoff 1971 points to contrasts like the following, as evidence.

(45) a. *Arizona elected Goldwater Senator, and Massachusetts McCormack Congressman.
  b. *Millie will send the President an obscene telegram, Paul the Queen a pregnant duck.
    (Jackendoff 1971 (23): 25)

But this effect is probably related to the fact that the remnants in Gapping constructions are used to introduce "new" information into the discourse, a point that Kuno 1976 draws attention to. One way this can express itself is for the remnants, and the parallel terms in the first conjunct - I will call them "correlates" from now on - to be focused. Gapping constructions can therefore be thought of as appropriate in contexts in which there is an implicit question that the remnants and correlates serve as answers to. (46), for example, might be thought of as addressing a topic that is expressed by the question: 'Who likes what?'.

(46) Jerry likes beans and Sally kumquats.

When sentences with Gaps in them are explicitly offered as answers to questions, it is much easier to have more than two remnants.

(47) Who will send who what?
  Sally will send Ron pickles, and Martha Hermione kumquats.

Or when the remnants have more descriptive content to them than names do, and are therefore more suitable for introducing new information, the results also improve.

(48) Arizona elected a right-wing bastard to the Senate and Massachusetts a moderate wank to the Congress.

This property of the construction probably also plays a role in examples that Hankamer 1973 judged unacceptable and credited to what he called the No Ambiguity Constraint. Some of his examples are in (49).

(49) a. Jack calls Joe Mike and Sam calls Joe Harry.
  b. Jack told Harry that Nixon was a fairy, and Alex told Harry that Agnew had warts.
  c. Max wanted to put the eggplant on the table, and Harvey wanted to put the eggplant in the sink.
  (Hankamer 1973 (57-9): 31)

Hankamer argued that these do not get the interpretation that would result from the pattern of Gapping shown because there is another interpretation available that blocks these. This other interpretation, which might be produced by Conjunction Reduction or Gapping or both, is indicated by the ellipses shown in (50).

(50) a. Jack calls Joe Mike and Jack calls Sam Harry.
  b. Jack told Harry that Nixon was a fairy, and Jack told Alex that Agnew had warts.
c. Max wanted to put the eggplant on the table, and Max wanted to put Alex in the sink.

Hankamer suggested that when Gapping produces ambiguous results, as in these cases, those interpretations which would place the Gap at the leftmost edge are favored, hence the interpretation in (50) but not (49). But Kuno 1976 argues that these contrasts too are an artefact of the requirement that Gapping remnants introduce new material.11 He points out that when names are used, the tendency already present to treat the material within VP as new information will be strengthened. This will, by itself favor, the interpretation in (49) over that in (50), since in neutral contexts the subjects of the first conjunct will not be taken to introduce new material and will, as a consequence, not be suitable correlates for remnants in the second conjunct. This tendency can be overcome, however, if the correlate status of the subject is signaled lexically, as in (51).

(51) a. Some call Joe Mike and others call Joe Harry.
  b. Some told Harry that Nixon was a fairy, and others told Harry that Agnew had warts.
  c. Some wanted to put the eggplant on the table, and others wanted to put the eggplant in the sink.

Or if the sentences are uttered with appropriate stress, placed on the subjects but not the objects; or if they are uttered in a context that makes it clear which arguments are furnishing new information.12

Here, then, is our second condition on the remnants:

(52) Kuno's Novelty Condition on Remnants
  The phrases in the coördinate that are left over from Gapping introduce new information.

This and the Constituency Condition on Remnants in (44) are the best candidates for constraints on what Gapping leaves behind. The remainder of the conditions on Gapping tend to be found in constraints on the strings that can Gap.

Ross and Hankamer took ellipses rules in general, and Gapping in particular, to be a phenomenon which deletes a "variable" in the structural description of a transformational rule. On this conception, the remnants could be thought of as "targets" in the transformational rule, and the variable that corresponds to the string surrounding these targets would be subject to the ellipsis process. Thus, the structural description could select maximal projections, accounting for the Constituency Condition on Remnants, and Gapping would delete the rest of the clause.13 Now this predicts that the constraints which Ross 1967, for example, identifies as holding of these variables should play a role in defining which strings Gapping can affect. Neijt 1979 is the fullest systematic study of this prediction, and she concludes that it is largely confirmed. Ross's constraints, later incorporated into more general constraints such as Subjacency, are now typically held to govern the distance that things can move. So one way of judging this thesis is to see if there is a match between the strings past which things can move and the strings that can Gap. This is essentially what Neijt sought. Some of her examples are in (53)-(55).

(53) a. *John came home to find his wife sick, and Bill came home to find his child sick.
    *My wife, who I came home to find sick, was in a lousy mood.
b. *John must be a fool to have married Jane, and Bill must be a fool to have married Martha.
  *The woman who John was a fool to have married was Jane.
c. *Tom went to Florida to learn to play tennis and Bill went to Florida tolearn to play squash.
  *What did Tom go to India to become.
d. ??John was upset having received A- for the course, and Bill was upset havingreceived B- for the course.
  ??What grade was John upset having received for the course?
  (Neijt 1979 (53): 131-2)
(54) a. *John wondered what to cook today and Peter wondered what to cook tomorrow.
    *When did John wonder what to cook?14
b. *John asked which candidates to interview this morning and Peter asked whichcandidates to interview this afternoon.
  *When did John ask which candidates to interview?
    (ibid (73):138)
(55) *John discussed my question of which flowers they saw and Bill discussed my question (of) which animals they saw.
  *Which flowers did John believe the claim that Peter saw?
  (ibid (56)/(64): 134 & 136)

In (53) we see instances of the Adjunct condition which prohibits movement out of an adjunct clause and will have the consequence of preventing Gapping from including part of an adjunct. In (54) are instances of the Wh Island Constraint, which prohibits movement out of indirect questions and here blocks Gaps from including part of an indirect question. And in (55) is an instance of the Complex Noun Phrase Constraint, which prevents movement out of clauses embedded within NPs, and would therefore prevent Gaps from similarly reaching into an NP.

Neijt also notes some differences between constraints on movement and those on Gapping. She notes, for instance, that Gapping cannot affect a string that reaches into a finite clause. There is a difference, then, between examples like (56) and those that Ross described (such as Ross's (57), in which Gapping reaches into a non-finite clause).

(56) a. *Charles decided that 20 boys are coming along and Harrie decided that 30 girls are coming along.
  b, *The first letter says that you should pay tax and the second letter says that you should pay V.A.T.
  (ibid (86): 142-3)
(57) I want to try to begin to write a novel, and Mary want to try to begin to write a play.

There is no visible corresponding constraint on movement in English; certainly wh Movement is not prevented from coming out of finite clauses:

(58) a. How many girls did Charles decide are coming along?
  b. What did the first letter say that you should pay?

Neijt suggests that Gapping is subject to Chomsky 1977's Tensed S Condition, which prohibits extraction from finite clauses. When this constraint applies to movement operations, as in (58), Chomsky argued that it can be satisfied if the moved phrase moves first into the Comp (or, Specifier of CP) position of the finite clause it is going to escape. He formulated the Tensed S Condition so that it could move things out of finite clauses only if they are in Comp: descriptively, at the left edge of the clause. That this particular formulation of the Tensed S Condition is at play in the Gapping construction, Neijt argues is indicated by the fact that when the remnant is in the Comp position of the finite clause, the result is improved. Thus, she contrasts (56) with the relatively grammatical (59).

(59) a. Charles may decided which boys are coming along and Max may decide which girls are coming along.
  b. The first letter says how much tax you should pay and the second letter says how much V.A.T. you should pay.
  (ibid (85): 142)

But there are problems with this way of characterizing such examples. The contrast between (56) and (59) is conceivably traced back to the availability of another ellipsis process restricted to questions. This process - also first systematically studied by John Ross15 - is known as Sluicing and exemplified by (60).

(60) I can remember which women Mary knows, but I can't recall which men Mary knows.

In general, Sluicing elides the sentence that follows a wh-phrase, when that elided sentence has an antecedent previous to it, and when certain conditions on contrastiveness are met.16 If Sluicing is capable of eliding just a portion of the sentence it affects, then examples like those in (59) could conceivably be produced through a combination of Gapping (eliding the main highest verbs of the conjunct) and Sluicing (eliding the material in the embedded interrogative).

Nonetheless, even if (59) are not produced by Gapping alone, Neijt's conjecture that Gapping obeys the Tensed S Condition remains consistent with the data. In general, then, her catalogue of facts supports the hypothesis that Gapping targets the class of strings that are allowed to lie between the target and landing site of a movement operation. In current syntactic theory, these strings are no longer characterized in terms of variables in the structural description of a transformational rule. Movement transformations are instead processes whose parts are partitioned out to independent modules of the grammar, and the constraints on the distances that movement operations may traverse are thought to emerge as a consequence of how these modules play out. A natural way of interpreting the match between what can Gap and what can be traversed by movement is that Gapping can act on the constituents that are formed by movement. This presently seems to be the consensus view: Gapping is capable of acting on the output of a movement operation that relocates remnants. Sag 1980 may have been the first to propose something along these lines. He suggests17 that the variable which Gapping deletes on the surface must correspond to a constituent formed at Logical Form by moving the remnants. He relates the movement of the remnants at Logical Form to their bearing focus, which he followed Chomsky 1980 in supposing induced a kind of Focus Movement.

Pesetsky 1982, who similarly concludes that the strings which Gap are formed by movement,18 brings forward additional data that fits this interpretation of the island effects in (53)-(55). He notes that not only are islands obeyed by the Gapped string, but that the strength of island violations is reproduced as well. For instance, there is a strong difference in violations of the wh-island condition that depends on the position from which the term escaping the island originates. Extraction of objects from wh-islands is considerably better than extraction of subjects, as the pair in (61) illustrates.

(61) a. ??Which food does this man know why you ate?
  b. *Which food does this man know why makes you sick?

This contrast is preserved in Gapping contexts.

(62) a. ??This man knows why you eat spaghetti, and that man, macaroni.
  b. *This man knows why spaghetti makes you sick, and that man, macaroni.
  (Pesetsky 1982 (120b): 644, (121): 645)

Further, Pesetsky argues that other constraints on multiple questions are found in Gapping. One of those constraints, Superiority, prevents wh-movement from moving a term past a c-commanding interrogative phrase. This is what is responsible for the contrast in grammaticality in (63).

(63) a. Who gave what to Mary?
  b. *What did who give to Mary?

Pesetsky reports a similar contrast for the remnants in Gapping. If one of those remnants is a wh-phrase, then it cannot have been moved past a c-commanding remnant; the contrast in (64) mirrors that in (63).19

(64) a. Bill asked which books I gave to Mary, and which records, to John.
  b. *Bill asked which books Mary likes, and which records, John.
  (Pesetsky 1982 (126), (127): 646)

It's unclear how to formulate Superiority so that it will cover both cases; but in general, the match between (63) and (64) suggests that a similar process is involved in creating both constructions. If the in situ wh-phrases in (63) move - a popular approach to these sorts of multiple questions - then the hypothesis that Gapping remnants move as well makes sense of the match.

Moreover, this thesis has the interesting side-effect that it explains the Constituency Condition on Remnants. To the extent that movement operations can only target constituents, they will pick out just those strings as remnants which parse as constituents. Moreover, it goes beyond the Constituency Condition and offers a method for blocking the bad examples in (37) and (38) as well. If remnants are just phrases that move, then the cases in (37b) and (38b) would have to arise by moving an NP away from its determiner, and this is not possible. To produce the ungrammatical (37c) and (38c), it would be necessary to move a DP out of a prepositional phrase, and though this is normally quite possible in English, there are movement operations which are constrained in this way. "Scrambling" in the Germanic languages, for instance, is incapable of stranding prepositions; indeed, Scrambling in the Germanic languages is blocked from moving constituents out of embedded finite clauses as well, matching in this respect the constraint on Gapping that (56) illustrates. Finally, Scrambling in the Germanic languages is plausibly able to move infinitival clauses (the evidence is unclear), but probably cannot move VPs out of embedded clauses. This would explain why embedded infinitival clauses can be remnants (as in (42a)) but embedded VPs cannot (as (42b) shows).

Thus, many of the constraints on remnants and on the strings that can Gap are accounted for if the thesis that Gapping can be fed by movement is given the more specific form in (65).

(65) Gapping elides an XP from which the remnants have scrambled.

Under this interpretation of the facts, examples such as (66) or (68) would have representations like (67) and (69).

(66) Some have drunk whiskey and others have drunk bourbon

(67)

(68) Some want to drink whiskey and others want to drink bourbon.

(69)

To produce examples like (8), repeated here as (70), we let Gapping elide the VP without accompanying scrambling, as in (71).

(70) Mary left early, and Sally left early too.

(71)

And to manufacture examples like (9), repeated below, we should adopt the thesis that subjects can be generated within the VP, and let (9) arise when the subject remains in this position, as in shown in (73).

(72) Jill ate rice yesterday and Jill ate porridge today.

(73)

By and large, then, if Gapping can elide VPs, and can do so after terms within that VP have scrambled out, a certain range of central cases can be accounted for.

The odd property of this thesis is that it requires English surface forms to be able to be produced by the Scrambling process that is so transparently a part of, say, German or Dutch word-order. English surface forms, however, do not otherwise appear to have been created by Scrambling. One of the unsolved problems of Gapping, then, is to fit the thesis in (65) to the more general syntax of English sentences, or to find a replacement for (65).

If such a fit can be found, however, the technique (65) allows can also be extended to cases such as (74), in which Gapping has elided the subject along with the verb.

(74) On Monday, I bought a car and on Tuesday I bought a motorcycle.
    (Oirsouw 1987, (158):146)

(Cases such as these are also found in Kuno (1976, (31a):307) and Sag (1980, (3.4.16):266).) If we assume that the topicalized PPs in this example are adjoined to IP, then we can combine the techniques used to manufacture (71) and (72) to give the Gap in (74) the representation in (75).

(75)

Through this case, another fact about Gapping can be observed: there is a matching requirement on the word order found in the antecedent clause, and the clause with the Gap.20 (76) is relatively ungrammatical when compared to (74).

(76) *I bought a car on Monday, and on Tuesday, a motorcycle.

This fact might be related to another requirement on Gapping: the scope of quantifiers in the antecedent clause must be parallel to those in the clause with the Gap. In (77), for example, if some girl has narrower scope than every book then some boy must also have scope narrower than every pamphlet.

(77) Some girl read every book and some boy every pamphlet.

If some boy has scope wider than every pamphlet, then some girl is going to have wider scope than every book. In other words, (77) does not support interpretations paraphrased in (78).

(78) a. There is some girl who read every book, and for each pamphlet, there is some boy or other who read it.
  b. For each book, there is some girl or other who read it, and there is some boy who read every pamphlet.

The same parallelism can be demonstrated for quantificational arguments which are included in the ellipsis, as in (79).

(79) Some read a story by Grimm to every child and others a story by Seuss.

Just as in (77), the relative scopes of every child and a story by Grimm must match the relative scopes of every child and a story by Seuss. A similar parallelism is found in other forms of ellipsis - VP ellipsis, pseudogapping and sluicing - and it is presently thought that the close relationship between ellipsis and deaccenting is responsible (see Fox 2000 and Merchant 2001). To the extent that word order expresses information structure, including the focus semantics of a clause, it may be possible to relate the matching requirement that (76) illustrates with the parallelism effect found in cases such as (77) and (79).

If the parallelism constraint on the scope of arguments that (77) and (79) illustrate is something that Gapping shares with other ellipsis processes, it also displays some unique scopal properties. Oehrle 1987, Siegel 1987 and McCawley 1993 note that modals and negation in the antecedent clause sometimes behave as if they scope over the entire conjunction. For example, in (80a), must is understood to scope over the coördination, producing the interpretation paraphrased by (80b).

(80) a. I tried it in both positions, one of which must have been the locked position and the other one the unlocked position, but it wouldn't work either way.
  b. I tried it in both positions, for which it must have been that one was locked and the other unlocked, but it wouldn't work either way.
  (McCawley 1993, (20g): 249)

The same is found for didn't in (81a), which favors an interpretation in which it has the entire conjunction in its scope, yielding the meaning (81b) indicates.

(81) a. Kim didn't play bingo and Sandy didn't sit at home all evening.
  b. not ((Kim played bingo) and (Sandy sat at home all evening))
  (Oehrle 1987, based on (28):205)

Siegel suggests that this fact emerges only when Gapping has affected just the modal or negation and nothing else. Thus, she points to a contrast between (80a) and (82), in which Gapping has removed can't along with the verb that follows.21

(82) Ward can't eat caviar and his guest can't eat beans
  (Siegel (1987) (3):53)

Indeed, unlike (80a), this sentence can be understood as synonymous with Ward can't eat caviar and his guests can't eat beans, in which can't is within each conjunct. It is also possible, however, to understand (82) so that can't has scope over the conjunction, that is, to be synonymous with (80a).

Perhaps related to these instances of surprising wide-scope are cases in which the subject of the antecedent clause takes an unexpectedly wide scope, as McCawley discovered by way of the example in (83); other examples, from Johnson 2000a, are (84).

(83) No one's1 duck was moist enough or his1 mussels tender enough.
    (McCawley (15a): 248)
(84) a. Not every girl1 ate a GREEN banana and her1 mother, a RIPE one.
  b. No boy1 joined the navy and his1 mother, the army.

In each of these cases, the quantificational subject of the first conjunct can, as indicated by the indices, bind the pronoun found in the second conjunct. This is normally not possible, as (85) shows, presumably because the contents of the second conjunct do not normally fall within the scope of the material in the first.

(85) a. *Not every girl1 ate a GREEN banana and her1 mother ate a RIPE one.
  b. *No boy1 joined the navy and his1 mother joined the army.

There is something about Gapping, then, that allows the material in the antecedent clause to have scope over the clause with the gap, and therefore, over the conjunction housing both clauses.

McCawley relates these latter examples of exceptional scope to another exotic property of Gapping. It is sometimes possible, he shows, for Gapping to elide a part of the subject along with the verb. Some of his examples are (86).

(86) a. Too many Irish setters are named Kelly and German shepherds, Fritz.
  b. The duck is dry and mussels, tough.
c. Your daughter is 16 and son, 17 ½.
d. How many states have a veterinary school or cities a zoo?
  (McCawley 1993 (1a,c,d): 245, (6a): 246)

McCawley argues that it's only terms in "determiner position" which are able to Gap in this way, pointing to the ungrammaticality of examples such as (87).

(87) a. Italian red wines are outstanding and white wines excellent
  b. Red wines from Italy are outstanding and white wines excellent.
  (ibid (10a', a''): 246)

The reason that McCawley connects these startling instances of Gapping with the puzzling wide-scope of the determiners in (83)/(84) is that, in some of these cases, the scope of the Gapped determiner also appears to be required to have wide-scope. For example, he points to (88a) and notes that it has a paraphrase something like (88b) rather than (88c).

(88) a. Not enough linguists study Russian, literary scholars French, or engineers Japanese.
  b. Not enough linguists, literary scholars and engineers study Russian, French and Japanese respectively.
  c. Not enough linguists study Russian or not enough literary scholars study French or not enough engineers study Japanese.
  (ibid (12a): 247)

The fact that the paraphrase involves conjunctions rather than the disjunctions the sentence actually uses indicates that the negation built into not enough has wide scope. The same thing can be seen in (89a), whose paraphrase in (89b) perhaps makes clearer the wide scope aspect to these cases.

(89) a. No cat should eat Puppy Chow or dog, Whiskers.
  b. It's not the case that any cat should eat Puppy Chow or that any dog should eat Whiskers.

It would seem, then, that the fact that quantificational determiners are capable of escaping the scope of the disjunction, or conjunction, in a Gapping context is a precondition for these instances of Gapping. This, perhaps, is why the determiner a seems unable to Gap in these contexts - another discovery in McCawley - since when a takes wide-scope it does so by means quite different from other quantifiers.

(90) *A soup was too salty and pie too sweet, but otherwise the food was outstanding.
  (ibid (5a): 245)

To fit these instances of determiner Gapping into the framework in (65) for understanding the constituency of gaps is quite a challenge. It would seem to require moving all of the subject, except its determiner, along with whatever other remnants there are, out of the VP, and then Gapping that VP. For some recent attempts at just that, see Lin 2001 and Johnson 2000a, b.

McCawley's paraphrase of (88a) in (88b) brings out another aspect of the Gapping construction: it has a superficial similarity to the use of respectively in coördinations. Not only does a Gapping sentence like (91a) mean something very like what (91b) means, they both involve focus on the related, compared, terms in a similar fashion.

(91) a. Jill ate beans and Jerry ate rice.
  b. Jill and Jerry and beans and rice respectively.

Moreover, the constraints on the strings that may Gap roughly match the constraints that the respectively construction places on the distance between the coördinated phrases that are being related. So, for instance, just as a string that includes a part of an adjunct clause cannot be Gapped (witness (92a)), so also is it impossible to relate two coördinates with respectively across an adjunct (as in (92b)).

(92) a. *Tom went to Florida to learn to play tennis and Bill went to Florida tolearn to play squash.
  b. *Tom and Bill went to Florida to learn to place tennis and squash respectively.

Similarly, respectively seems unable to relate coördinates that are separated by a finite clause in the same way that (56) (repeated here) indicates that Gapping cannot reach into a finite clause.

(93) a. *Charles decided that 20 boys are coming along and Harrie decided that 30 girls are coming along.
  b. *Charles and Harrie decided that 20 boys and 30 girls are coming along respectively.

The match isn't perfect, respectively can apply to a coördinated argument within a prepositional phrase, as in (94a) and, as we've seen, Gapping cannot target a remnant in this position (compare (94b)).

(94) a. John and Jill stood beside Jim and Mary respectively.
  b. ?*John stood beside Jim and Jill stood beside Mary.

Still, to a large degree, the constraints on these two constructions are the same. This has led some to attempt to derive one construction directly from the other (see Hudson 1976 and Moltmann 1992 for extended analyses along these lines, and Dougherty 1970, 1971, Goodall 1987 and Muadz 1991 for some relevant discussion). Another coherent approach, however, would be to give to both Gapping and respectively a syntax that triggers the same family of constraints.22

In summary, Gapping is a process that elides VPs from which remnants have moved, sometimes by Scrambling. Unlike other ellipses processes, Gapping is found only in coördinations and is uniquely subject to the No Embedding Constraint.

Notes

1 To see Gapping playing a role in (3), one must imagine the VP met kids following than out of which met has Gapped.

2 See Dougherty 1970, 1971 and Burton and Grimshaw 1992 among others.

3 Chinese has the interesting property of favoring instances of Gapping like these over the more familiar ones in (1), suggesting that these two cases are not completely identical. See Paul 1999 for discussion.

4 And see Munn 1993 for a more recent treatment along these lines.

5 Though, see Sag 1980 for reasons for thinking that an independent ellipsis process is responsible (and Neijt 1979 p. 57ff for counterarguments).

6 A point also made by Chomsky 1980, p. 190.

7 This issue concerning the distinction between Deletion and N Gapping is the discussed in Jackendoff 1971.

8 To find contexts in which Adverbs or Complementizers (such as whether or that) Gap is not possible (because no material within and Adverbial Phrase or Complementizer Phrase can stand to the left of an Adverb or Complementizer), so whether these categories can Gap is undeterminable.

9 His examples are slightly different than mine, but not meaningfully. See Sag 1980 p. 273.

10 This is how the constraint is commonly framed, but Jackendoff 1971, p. 26 expresses it as follows: "In by far the most acceptable examples of Gapping, then, there is only one unlike constituent in the second verb phrase, and all the rest must delete."

11 In combination with various processing pressures.

12 For other problems with the No Ambiguity Constraint, see Sag 1980, p. 211ff, Langendoen 1976, Stillings 1975, Quirk et al. 1972 and Quirk et al. 1972, p. 580ff.

13 This is essentially how Sag 1980 formulates the process, which he then couples with a version of Bresnan 1976 Relativized A-over-A Condition to capture some of the cases that Hankamer's Major Constituent requirement was aimed at.

14 This, and the question corresponding to (54b), are ungrammatical on the construal in which when comes from the embedded clause.

15 See Ross 1969.

16 For a recent analysis of Sluicing, see Chung et al. 1994 and Merchant 2001.

17 See Sag 1980, p. 288.

18 He conjectured that the movement operation occurred on the surface, not at Logical Form as in Sag's work, and that the remnants were moved into Comp position (what would in present terminology be the Specifier of CP).

19 I don't find the contrast in (64) as strong as that in (63).

20 A constraint pointed out in Hankamer 1979 and Pesetsky 1982, p. 658.

21 It should be noted that Gapping is not always successfully able to affect strings with negation in them. Ross 1970, for instance, points to cases like (i) and suggests that Gapping is generally incapable of eliding not.

(i) *I didn't eat fish, Bill didn't eat rice, and Harry didn't eat roast beef.

See also Jackendoff 1971, Stillings 1975 and Sag 1980, p. 195.

22 See Beck 2000 for an approach along these lines.



Return to SynCom Working Directory

Last Updated December 12, 2001 by Rob Goedemans

Valid HTML 4.01!